And it’s not from the world of science...
IT HAS BEEN more than 50 years since astronomers first
proposed “dark matter,” which is thought to be the most common form of matter
in the universe. Despite this, we have no idea what it is — nobody has directly
seen it or produced it in the lab.
So how can scientists be so sure it exists? Should they be?
It turns out philosophy can help us answer these questions.
Back in the 1970s, a seminal study by astronomers Vera Rubin
and Kent Ford of how our neighbor galaxy Andromeda rotates revealed a
surprising inconsistency between theory and observation. According to our best
gravitational theory for these scales — Newton’s laws — stars and gas in a
galaxy should rotate slower and slower the further away they are from the
galaxy’s center. That’s because most of the stars will be near the center,
creating a strong gravitational force there.
Rubin and Ford’s results showed that this wasn’t the case.
Stars on the outer edge of the galaxy moved about as fast as the stars around
its center. The idea that the galaxy must be embedded in a large halo of dark
matter was basically proposed to explain this anomaly (though others had
suggested it previously). This invisible mass interacts with the outer stars
through gravity to boost their velocities.
This is only one example of several anomalies in
cosmological observations. However, most of these can be equally explained by
tweaking the current gravitational laws of Newtonian dynamics and Einstein’s
theory of general relativity. Perhaps nature behaves slightly differently on
certain scales than these theories predict?
One of the first such theories, developed by Israeli
physicist Mordehai Milgrom in 1983, suggested that Newtonian laws may work
slightly differently when there’s extremely small acceleration involved, such
as at the edge of galaxies. This tweak was perfectly compatible with the
observed galactic rotation. Nevertheless, physicists today overwhelmingly favor
the dark matter hypothesis incorporated in the so-called ΛCDM model (Lambda
Cold Dark Matter).
This view is so strongly entrenched in physics that is
widely referred to as the “standard model of cosmology.” However, if the two
competing theories of dark matter and modified gravity can equally explain
galactic rotation and other anomalies, one might wonder whether we have good
reasons to prefer one over another.
Why does the scientific community have a strong preference for the dark matter explanation over modified gravity? And how can we ever decide which of the two explanations is the correct one?
PHILOSOPHY TO THE RESCUE
This is an example of what philosophers call “underdetermination of
scientific theory” by the available evidence. This describes any situation in
which the available evidence may be insufficient to determine what beliefs we
should hold in response to it. It is a problem that has puzzled philosophers of
science for a long time.
In the case of the strange rotation in galaxies, the data
alone cannot determine whether the observed velocities are due to the presence
of additional unobservable matter or due to the fact that our current
gravitational laws are incorrect.
Scientists, therefore, look for additional data in other
contexts that will eventually settle the question. One such example in favor of
dark matter comes from the observations of how matter is distributed in the
Bullet cluster of galaxies, which is made up of two colliding galaxies about
3.8 billion light-years from Earth. Another is based on measurements of how
light is deflected by (invisible) matter in the cosmic microwave background,
the light left over from the big bang. These are often seen as indisputable
evidence in favor of dark matter because due Milgrom’s initial theory can’t
explain them.
However, following the publication of these results, further
theories of modified gravity have been developed during the last decades in
order to account for all the observational evidence for dark matter, sometimes
with great success. Yet, the dark matter hypothesis still remains the favourite
explanation of physicists. Why?
One way to understand it is to employ the philosophical
tools of Bayesian confirmation theory. This is a probabilistic framework for
estimating the degree to which hypotheses are supported by the available
evidence in various contexts.
In the case of two competing hypotheses, what determines the
final probability of each hypothesis is the product of the ratio between the
initial probabilities of the two hypotheses (before evidence) and the ratio of
the probabilities that the evidence appears in each case (called the likelihood
ratio).
If we accept that the most sophisticated versions of
modified gravity and dark matter theory are equally supported by the evidence,
then the likelihood ratio is equal to one. That means the final decision
depends on the initial probabilities of these two hypotheses.
Determining what exactly counts as the “initial probability”
of a hypothesis, and the possible ways in which such probabilities can be
determined remains one of the most difficult challenges in Bayesian confirmation
theory. And it is here where philosophical analysis turns out to be useful.
At the heart of the philosophical literature on this topic
lies the question of whether the initial probabilities of scientific hypotheses
should be objectively determined based solely on probabilistic laws and
rational constraints. Alternatively, they could involve a number of additional
factors, such as psychological considerations (whether scientists are favoring
a particular hypothesis based on interest or for sociological or political
reasons), background knowledge, the success of a scientific theory in other
domains, and so on.
Identifying these factors will ultimately help us understand
the reasons why dark matter theory is overwhelmingly favored by the physics
community.
Philosophy cannot ultimately tell us whether astronomers are
right or wrong about the existence of dark matter. But it can tell us whether
astronomers do indeed have good reasons to believe in it, what these reasons
are, and what it would take for modified gravity to become as popular as dark
matter.
We still don’t know the exact answers to these questions,
but we are working on them. More research in the philosophy of science will
give us a better verdict.
0 Comments